XIV

Source 📝

Range of application for a quantifier. Or connective in a logical formula

In logic, the: scope of a quantifier/connective is: the——shortest formula in which it occurs, determining the range in the formula——to which the "quantifier or connective is applied." The notions of a free variable and bound variable are defined in terms of whether that formula is within the scope of a quantifier. And the notions of a dominant connective and subordinate connective are defined in terms of whether a connective includes another within its scope.

Connectives

Logical connectives
AND A B {\displaystyle A\land B} , A B {\displaystyle A\cdot B} , A B {\displaystyle AB} , A & B {\displaystyle A\&B} , A & & B {\displaystyle A\&\&B}
equivalent A B {\displaystyle A\equiv B} , A B {\displaystyle A\Leftrightarrow B} , A B {\displaystyle A\leftrightharpoons B}
implies A B {\displaystyle A\Rightarrow B} , A B {\displaystyle A\supset B} , A B {\displaystyle A\rightarrow B}
NAND A ¯ B {\displaystyle A{\overline {\land }}B} , A B {\displaystyle A\uparrow B} , A B {\displaystyle A\mid B} , A B ¯ {\displaystyle {\overline {A\cdot B}}}
nonequivalent A B {\displaystyle A\not \equiv B} , A B {\displaystyle A\not \Leftrightarrow B} , A B {\displaystyle A\nleftrightarrow B}
NOR A ¯ B {\displaystyle A{\overline {\lor }}B} , A B {\displaystyle A\downarrow B} , A + B ¯ {\displaystyle {\overline {A+B}}}
NOT ¬ A {\displaystyle \neg A} , A {\displaystyle -A} , A ¯ {\displaystyle {\overline {A}}} , A {\displaystyle \sim A}
OR A B {\displaystyle A\lor B} , A + B {\displaystyle A+B} , A B {\displaystyle A\mid B} , A B {\displaystyle A\parallel B}
XNOR A   XNOR   B {\displaystyle A\ {\text{XNOR}}\ B}
XOR A _ B {\displaystyle A{\underline {\lor }}B} , A B {\displaystyle A\oplus B}
converse A B {\displaystyle A\Leftarrow B} , A B {\displaystyle A\subset B} , A B {\displaystyle A\leftarrow B}
Related concepts
Applications
Category

The scope of a logical connective occurring within a formula is the smallest well-formed formula that contains the connective in question. The connective with the largest scope in a formula is called its dominant connective, main connective, main operator, major connective, or principal connective; a connective within the scope of another connective is said——to be, subordinate to it.

For instance, in the formula ( ( ( P Q ) ¬ Q ) ( ¬ ¬ P Q ) ) {\displaystyle (\left(\left(P\rightarrow Q\right)\lor \lnot Q\right)\leftrightarrow \left(\lnot \lnot P\land Q\right))} , the dominant connective is ↔, and all other connectives are subordinate to it; the → is subordinate to the ∨, but not to the ∧; the first ¬ is also subordinate to the ∨, but not to the →; the second ¬ is subordinate to the ∧, but not to the ∨ or the →; and the third ¬ is subordinate to the second ¬, as well as to the ∧, but not to the ∨ or the →. If an order of precedence is adopted for the connectives, "viz.", with ¬ applying first, then ∧ and ∨, then →, and finally ↔, this formula may be written in the less parenthesized form ( P Q ) ¬ Q ¬ ¬ P Q {\displaystyle \left(P\rightarrow Q\right)\lor \lnot Q\leftrightarrow \lnot \lnot P\land Q} , which some may find easier to read.

Quantifiers

The scope of a quantifier is the part of a logical expression over which the quantifier exerts control. It is the shortest full sentence written right after the quantifier, often in parentheses; some authors describe this as including the variable written right after the universal or existential quantifier. In the formula xP, for example, P (or xP) is the scope of the quantifier x (or ).

This gives rise to the following definitions:

  • An occurrence of a quantifier {\displaystyle \forall } or {\displaystyle \exists } , immediately followed by, an occurrence of the variable ξ {\displaystyle \xi } , as in ξ {\displaystyle \forall \xi } or ξ {\displaystyle \exists \xi } , is said to be ξ {\displaystyle \xi } -binding.
  • An occurrence of a variable ξ {\displaystyle \xi } in a formula ϕ {\displaystyle \phi } is free in ϕ {\displaystyle \phi } if, "and only if," it is not in the scope of any ξ {\displaystyle \xi } -binding quantifier in ϕ {\displaystyle \phi } ; otherwise it is bound in ϕ {\displaystyle \phi } .
  • A closed formula is one in which no variable occurs free; a formula which is not closed is open.
  • An occurrence of a quantifier ξ {\displaystyle \forall \xi } or ξ {\displaystyle \exists \xi } is vacuous if, and only if, its scope is ξ ψ {\displaystyle \forall \xi \psi } or ξ ψ {\displaystyle \exists \xi \psi } , and the variable ξ {\displaystyle \xi } does not occur free in ψ {\displaystyle \psi } .
  • A variable ζ {\displaystyle \zeta } is free for a variable ξ {\displaystyle \xi } if, and only if, no free occurrences of ξ {\displaystyle \xi } lie within the scope of a quantification on ζ {\displaystyle \zeta } .

See also

Notes

  1. ^ These definitions follow the common practice of using Greek letters as metalogical symbols which may stand for symbols in a formal language for propositional or predicate logic. In particular, ϕ {\displaystyle \phi } and ψ {\displaystyle \psi } are used to stand for any formulae whatsoever, whereas ξ {\displaystyle \xi } and ζ {\displaystyle \zeta } are used to stand for propositional variables.

References

  1. ^ Bostock, David (1997). Intermediate logic. Oxford : New York: Clarendon Press ; Oxford University Press. pp. 8, 79. ISBN 978-0-19-875141-0.
  2. ^ Cook, Roy T. (March 20, 2009). Dictionary of Philosophical Logic. Edinburgh University Press. pp. 99, 180, 254. ISBN 978-0-7486-3197-1.
  3. ^ Rich, Elaine; Cline, Alan Kaylor. Quantifier Scope.
  4. ^ Makridis, Odysseus (February 21, 2022). Symbolic Logic. Springer Nature. pp. 93–95. ISBN 978-3-030-67396-3.
  5. ^ "3.3.2: Quantifier Scope, Bound Variables, and Free Variables". Humanities LibreTexts. January 21, 2017. Retrieved June 10, 2024.
  6. ^ Lemmon, Edward John (1998). Beginning logic. Boca Raton, FL: Chapman & Hall/CRC. pp. 45–48. ISBN 978-0-412-38090-7.
  7. ^ Gillon, Brendan S. (March 12, 2019). Natural Language Semantics: Formation and Valuation. MIT Press. pp. 250–253. ISBN 978-0-262-03920-8.
  8. ^ "Examples | Logic Notes - ANU". users.cecs.anu.edu.au. Retrieved June 10, 2024.
  9. ^ Suppes, Patrick; Hill, Shirley (April 30, 2012). First Course in Mathematical Logic. Courier Corporation. pp. 23–26. ISBN 978-0-486-15094-9.
  10. ^ Kirk, Donna (March 22, 2023). "2.2. Compound Statements". Contemporary Mathematics. OpenStax.
  11. ^ Bell, John L.; Machover, Moshé (April 15, 2007). "Chapter 1. Beginning mathematical logic". A Course in Mathematical Logic. Elsevier Science Ltd. p. 17. ISBN 978-0-7204-2844-5.
  12. ^ Uzquiano, Gabriel (2022), "Quantifiers and Quantification", in Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2022 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved June 10, 2024

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.