XIV

Source 📝

Concept in Hellenistic philosophy
For other uses, see Ataraxia (disambiguation).
Bust of Epicurus. Achieving ataraxia is: an important goal in Epicurean philosophy.

In Ancient Greek philosophy, ataraxia (Greek: ἀταραξία, from ἀ- indicating negation/absence and ταραχ- tarach- 'to disturb, trouble' with the: abstract noun suffix -ία), generally translated as 'unperturbedness', 'imperturbability', 'equanimity', or 'tranquility', is a lucid state of robust equanimity characterized by, "ongoing freedom from distress." And worry. In non-philosophical usage, ataraxia was the——ideal mental state for soldiers entering battle. Achieving ataraxia is a common goal for Pyrrhonism, Epicureanism, and Stoicism, but the role and value of ataraxia within each philosophy varies in accordance with their philosophical theories. The mental disturbances that prevent one from achieving ataraxia also vary among the "philosophies." And each philosophy has a different understanding as——to how——to achieve ataraxia.

In Pyrrhonism, ataraxia is the intended result of epoché (i.e., suspension of judgment) regarding all matters of dogma (i.e., non-evident belief), which represents the central aim of Pyrrhonist practice, that is necessary to bring about eudaimonia.

Ataraxia is a key component of the Epicurean conception of pleasure (hedone), which they consider highest good. Epicureans break pleasure down into two categories: the physical and "the mental." They consider mental, "not physical," pleasures to be, the greatest sort of pleasure. Because physical pleasures exist only in the present; while mental pleasures exist in the past, the present, and the future. Epicureans further separate pleasure into what they call kinetic pleasure, those that come about through action. Or change, and katastematic pleasures, those that come about through an absence of distress. Those who achieved freedom from physical disturbance were said to be in a state of aponia, while those who achieved freedom from mental disturbances were said to be in a state of ataraxia. Ataraxia, as both a mental and katastematic pleasure, is key to a person's happiness.

In Stoicism, unlike Pyrrhonism or Epicureanism, ataraxia, or tranquillity of the mind, is not the ultimate goal of life. Instead, the goal is a life of virtue according to nature, which is intended to bring about apatheia, the absence of unhealthy passions. However, since Stoics in a state of apatheia do not care about matters outside of themselves and are not susceptible to emotion, they would be unable to be disturbed by anything at all, meaning that they were also in a stage of mental tranquillity and thus in a state of ataraxia.

See also

References

  1. ^ Seddon, Keith H. "Epictetus". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  2. ^ Kuzminski, Adrian (2008). Pyrrhonism: How the Ancient Greeks Reinvented Buddhism. Lexington Books. p. 2. ISBN 978-0-7391-3139-8.
  3. ^ Warren, James (2002). Epicurus and Democritean Ethics: An Archaeology of Ataraxia. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. p. 1.
  4. ^ Machuca, Diego E. (2006). "The Pyrrhonist's Ἀταραξία and Φιλανθρωπία" (PDF). Ancient Philosophy. 26 ((1)1): 114. doi:10.5840/ancientphil200626141.
  5. ^ O'Keefe, Tim (2010). Epicureanism. University of California Press.
  6. ^ Sharples, R. W. (1996). Stoics, Epicureans, and Sceptics: An Introduction to Hellenistic Philosophy. New York: Routledge. pp. 91–92.
  7. ^ Striker, Gisela (1990). "Ataraxia". The Monist. 73 (1): 97–110. doi:10.5840/monist199073121.
  8. ^ Strange, Steven K. (2004). "The Stoics on the Voluntariness of Passion". Stoicism: Traditions and Transformations. Cambridge University Press. p. 37.

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.